by Simon Smith
Many things go through a fellow’s mind when he’s checking
the proofs of his book, hunting down the last few typos (nasty little beggars,
hiding among the black type and white space). Things like, ‘Is that really how that’s spelled?’, ‘Are there such things as philosophy
groupies?’, ‘What the hell is that
supposed to mean?’ and, most significantly of all, ‘Is it lunchtime yet?’
A thing which
shambled back and forth across my fevered mind made me grin cynically. It was a
reviewer’s comment to the effect that, while the logic of my arguments was
perfectly sound, readers would still, no doubt, disagree with the conclusions.
I mention this, not by way of criticism. Quite the opposite, in fact; it was an
extremely perspicacious remark. It tells us everything we need to know about
philosophers, academics, perhaps even real people. (Another important clue to
human nature may be the mushroom cloud, which is doubtless hovering over
Southeast Asia e’er now.) The reasoning may be fine, but we are not convinced.
Perhaps, we’re not as rational as we think. But let’s not get hung up on the
supposed rationality of philosophical minds. Academia is home to many a
narcissistic sociopath, dipsomaniac, pill-popper, and sex pest; ratio animalis hardly gets a look in.
Another thought,
less cynical but more philosophical, concerned something I had forgotten to say
about Peter Byrne. I spent the whole first chapter going to work on Byrne’s God and Realism (Ashgate, 2003) in order
to show what a load of old toot it really is. Don’t get me wrong, I like
Byrne’s book, it’s an excellent resource. Not, perhaps, the very best but
representative of a type. God and Realism
is a master-class in realist metaphysics and, most importantly, everything
that’s wrong with it. Much of the old toot is the genuine article and turns up
in every attempt to formulate philosophical realism. To be fair to Byrne,
however, there’s plenty of original old toot there too; his contribution to the
incoherence of realism cannot be gainsaid.
Having spent
no little time dismembering Byrne’s so-called Innocent Realism, however, I
forgot to say that, in the end, he’s actually right about something rather
important.
Byrne’s point,
in case anyone hasn’t read his book, is that theistical language is essentially
realist. (This, despite explicitly stating that Innocent Realism is not
remotely concerned with language; all he cares about is what actually exists.) We are told that to
speak of God is (at the very least, to attempt) to refer to a mind-independent
reality: the Creator of Heaven and Earth and all the rest of it.
Just here, the
well-brought-up reader may be thinking, ‘Well, of course it is. The logic of
theism has to be realist because it’s an attempt to refer to a Reality, which,
putatively, is the creator of everything, including what we call “mentality”.’
Fair point. A Creator must be mind-independent, which is to say ontologically
prior to, his or her Creation. Hardly an example of reasoning at its most
sophisticated, but it’s fine as far as it goes, possibly. The trouble is, it
doesn’t actually go very far.
The underlying
obsession with things is, frankly,
weird. It hints of clammy hands and a sinister glint in the eye. The reliance
on necessitarian logic is a more serious problem. On its own terms, realism can be the only possible answer to the problem. Behind the acts and accidents
of Creation there must be a Being
such that… and so on and so forth. Ontological priority must be the only possible answer because if there’s another, then
the inference back from the contingencies of actual existence to Creative
Agency breaks down. And it’s not just the inference that’s in trouble; the
logic of ‘God-talk’ toto caelo is
undermined. To talk of God cannot, after all, be to talk of one contingent
being among others, it must, absolutely
must, be to talk of a Being whose existence cannot not be.
That’s all
very well, except the realist’s overcooked inference is not the only possible answer. Consider the ways in which our
intentions, far from being inevitably pre-fabricated, are frequently formed in
the enactment of them; consider, for example, the ways in which ideas take
shape in their expression, or explanation or, better still, the discussion. How
often do our thoughts only really become clear when we talk them through with
friends? Isn’t that the point of writing books and blogs and everything else,
at least in part?
Let’s not get
sidetracked. The point is, Byrne’s right: theism has to be realist; indeed it
does. That’s why theism necessarily deconstructs itself. Separating Divine Will
from Acts Creative and Providential strips Divinity of all its predicates, so
breaks the back of personal analogies. It pushes its own logic to breaking
point and beyond. And what does it leave us with?
‘Being-just-being-itself-in-plenitude’, that’s the expression I borrowed from
Farrer. What does it mean? Not a great deal.
It’s this, in
the end, which leaves theism defenceless against the ‘vulgar empiricism’, as
Feuerbach termed it (The Essence of
Christianity, Harper & Row, 1957), which persists in asking logically
indecent questions like ‘does (really) God exist?’
Tellingly,
empiricism, particularly in the guise of the modern sciences, is essentially
idealist, as John Macmurray (The Self as
Agent, Faber and Faber, 1957) and Michael Polanyi (Personal Knowledge, U. of
Chicago, 1974) have shown. Everyone knows that the demand for sensory
experience made science kin to the sense-datum philosophies which flourished at
the beginning of the 20th Century. What carried it beyond mere
phenomenalism, however, was its commitment to the diagrammatic nature of
reality. The sciences present us with maps of the universe, which have, thus
far, been extremely useful for finding our way about, as it were. Insofar as
they are useful – i.e. as they enable us to control, direct, and therefore
understand the universe – we consider them accurate. Whether or not they
correspond to a reality ‘beyond’ or ‘beneath’ the maps is hardly relevant and
certainly of no concern of the scientist.
The sciences
only get into trouble when they forget the diagrammatic nature of their
universe and suppose their maps are real in and of themselves. Indeed, the
scientist who imagines her epistemic tools are the only epistemic tools an
enquiring mind, an enlightened mind, could ever need, has abandoned science in
favour of philosophy, and bad philosophy at that. She has committed the
cardinal error of aping theism and thinking her discipline a realist one.
(Given how very critical of philosophy some scientists are, it’s curious how very
eager they are to have a go.) Being somewhat more tidy-minded, the sciences
generally get rid of all the mapmakers first, those diagrammatising minds, who
lie behind their diagrams. So goes the deconstruction of scientific thought.
In A Science of God? (Geoffrey Bles Ltd.
1966), Farrer referred to the scientist who followed this rocky path,
convincing herself that any reality her tools cannot discover is no reality at
all, as a ‘small-minded scientist’. Interestingly, the idea that so unscientific creature could actually
exist, particularly these days, he laughed to scorn. The ‘small-minded
scientist,’ he insisted, was a bit of foolish caricature.
Ahem.
That, of course, is not the end
of the story for any kind of enquiring mind. The scientist’s corrective is
simple enough: get back to work and stop fussing about questions which don’t
concern her. Theism, however, has a more difficult road ahead. The theist, or
theistical philosopher, cannot simply ‘get back to work’; not, at least,
without wilfully ignoring the logical and empirical disintegration of his
metaphysics. Naturally, the philosopher who would choose bad philosophy and
worse theology – not to mention a pernicious psychology – over a healthy and
inclusivist alternative is, I suppose, as much a caricature as Farrer’s
‘small-minded scientist’. Besides, theism, or more simply, religious faith, is
far too important to leave in clutches of that ‘vulgar empiricism’; for lived
faith is personality writ large. Where deconstruction occurs, reconstruction will
surely follow. And thanks to the likes of Farrer and Feuerbach we have far
better tools to work with. That, however, is a thought for another day.
No comments:
Post a Comment