Ricoeur’s Reconsideration of Personalism
A New
Perspective
by Dries Deweer
Ricoeur
was considered a representative of the personalist movement in his younger
years. Nevertheless, he later also supported the criticisms on personalism. The
extent to which Ricoeur succeeded in integrating these two elements – loyalty
and criticism – in his work shows us a way of regarding personalism as a
tenable philosophical position and an important input in contemporary
philosophy. In my chapter I analyze Ricoeur’s criticism of personalism, in
order to show – against the dominant interpretation – how his work ultimately
remains loyal to the personalist movement by developing a hermeneutical
phenomenology of the human person that answers the problems of personalism in a
way that respects its core ideas. These problems are:
(1) the neglect of the difference
between interpersonal and institutional relations:
The
personalist and communitarian ideal displayed the inclination to think of
communities after the example of direct interpersonal relationships. Mounier
and Maritain considered communities to be an extrapolation of friendship. Along
the same line, Scheler presented his community ideal of the so-called Gesamtperson as kind of relationship of
love. Ricoeur warned about the dangers of such an ideal of the small community.
For, the distinction between politics and ethics is implicitly wiped out, while
the distribution of power that is essential to politics is a matter of justice
and not a matter of friendship or love. Besides, it also restricts the idea of
a community to relations with persons with a face, persons with whom we can
relate in a direct way. Hence, personalism curbs the enlargement of the idea of
a community to institutional relations with any anonymous fellow human being,
the enlargement to relationships where the other has no face, but nevertheless
has rights.
(2) the lack of conceptual clarity:
Ricoeur
observed that personalism, despite all good intentions, had never reached the
same degree of conceptual clarity as the doctrines that it was supposed to
match.
(3) the vulnerability to
structuralist criticism:
Ricoeur
found that personalism, by putting itself in the line with doctrines such as
existentialism and Marxism, was exposed to the crushing criticism of
structuralism. Structuralism characterized all of these doctrines as instances
of humanism, in others words as doctrines that see the subject and its history
at the source of meaning. This perspective was subverted by the structuralist
focus on underlying systems where the meaning of social reality is produced by
the differential relations within the totality of the system itself,
independent of particular persons and the history that is determined by these
systems. This new approach of philosophy seemed to make the subject and its
history philosophically irrelevant, and with it all preceding philosophical
currents that were founded on these elements, such as personalism.
(4) the dependence on a fixed
Christian hierarchy of values:
The
Nietzschean footing of contemporary philosophy implies a frontal attack on the
Christian foundations of the concept of the person and the Christian value
absolutism. With regard to this criticism, Ricoeur had especially Jacques
Maritain and Max Scheler in mind, two personalist philosophers that explicitly
characterized their personalism as a Christian philosophy. Although Ricoeur
acknowledged that Mounier remained uncommitted in this regard, in order to
allow both Christian and agnostic interpretations, he was convinced that this
effort was in vain. One way or another personalism fell victim to the nihilist
devaluation of all higher values.
I
argue that Ricoeur eventually answers all four of these problems in his own
reconsideration of personalism. The first problem finds an answer in Ricoeur’s
distinction between the socius and
the neighbor, which he later
elaborated in the threefold structure of his so-called little ethics. The
second problem was resolved in the dissociation of the concept of the person
from the personalist doctrine, by means of the characterization of personhood
as an attitude. The third problem was addressed by Ricoeur’s confrontation with
structuralism as a necessary detour for a new understanding of the human
person. Finally, Ricoeur took the edge off the fourth problem by presenting
personal commitment as a matter of a risky conviction that makes the person
commit himself to a transcendent cause that only receives a hierarchical value
on the basis of the commitment itself.
No comments:
Post a Comment