by Simon Smith
Once again, combining a deeply
and dangerously repressed nature with heavy medication has done the trick.
Those chthonic memories of sex in the classroom are, once again, back in their
mouldy old oblong boxes, where they belong.
The point I
was trying to get at last time – and missed by a country mile – is whether or
not the specialisations and fragmentations of academic philosophy, and especially
ethics, really amount to very much. Do these divisions demarcate a boundary
line between kinds of principles and ways of thinking, or are they just
contextual markers? In either case, it seems fair to say that, if nothing else,
these divisions serve to focus the attention on some of the most basic moral
questions, such as “is it acceptable to treat people as though they were
objects in some way?” (In case you’re wondering, the answer is “no”; and if you
are wondering, what on earth are you
doing here?)
Take, for
example, the relatively new and relatively exciting world of neuroethics. Now,
this is a field that our friends Drs Beauregard and Larrivee have been
ploughing for some considerable time and, naturally, we bow to their expertise
in all matters pertaining thereto. Even if we leave aside all the frankly
nonsensical claims that MRI scanners can read minds, the modern neurosciences
still do throw up a number of serious ethical issues. Not a few of them seem to
come back, ultimately, to the compatibility of neurosciences’ flattened
materialism with the moral demands supposedly being made upon it.
I say
“supposedly” because I’m reasonably confident that even the most hard-bitten
materialist – he who denies the reality of anything other than physical forces
colliding and conditioning one another all over the place – could be delivered
of a genuine moral response with sufficient provocation. One would imagine that
almost any item in the news at the moment would do the trick; but that might
prove too abstract. Publicly declaring him or her to be an unprincipled,
plagiarising purveyor of voodoo and snake oil might do it. Or you could just
call him or her a ****.
The question,
however, remains: ‘is neuroethics a real specialism?’ The argument seems to be that
it must be, because, in order to do it properly, one has to know an enormous
amount complicated neuroscience. But is that really true, I wonder. It depends,
I suppose, on exactly what we mean when we say it.
On the one
hand, the question seems to be whether we need to know and understand all the
neuroscience – which, I’m assured by Dr. B, is very complicated indeed – in
order to understand the moral issues and do the moral thinking required. Insist
that we do, that sound moral thinking here depends on detailed knowledge of the
neurological context, and the neuroscientifically uninitiated are surely
entitled to ask precisely what and where are the special moral problems which
only neuroscientists can grapple with. On present showing they don’t seem too much
in evidence. More seriously, perhaps, given the tendency of neuroscientists to
turn up in law courts, what special moral training does the neuroscientist have
and where did he or she come by it? Philosophy in general and ethics in
particular is not, as a rule, a part of the average neuroscientists’ education.
No one doubts that many a neuroethicist is pretty hot stuff,
neuroscientifically speaking – no one, except, perhaps other neuroethicists.
But what, then, makes them so sure that they know what they’re talking about,
when it comes to morality?
On the other
hand, the question might be whether we need to know all the complicated
neuroscience in order to identify the moral issues and fully understand their
implications. A “yes” here would sound a lot more plausible. Obviously, it’s
difficult to see or even imagine what problems might be raised in this context
if one has no clue as to what actually goes on within it. Certainly, Dr. B has
intimated to me that this is a common view among the initiated.
And yet, it
doesn’t really change anything. It is, I think, still quite reasonable to ask
what special moral training the neuroethicist has had which enables him or her
to spot neuroethical problems and then tackle them. If, as often seems to be
the case, the answer is “none at all”, then even as we admire the
neuroethicist’s gung-ho attitude in being prepared to take on questions he or
she is singularly unequipped to take on, we cannot help wondering what makes
them so sure that their neuroethical questions really are so special after all.
One might even
suppose, if one were being especially cynical, that neuroethics as a distinct
discipline and, above all, publishing opportunity, has arisen owing to the
spectacular inability of its practitioners to articulate their moral questions
with sufficient clarity.
Chilly
misanthropy towards fellow scholars is unbecoming, however; and does no one any
good. The point here is not to suggest that the learning needed to understand
the neurological context can simply be dispensed with, any more than the
context itself can. Nevertheless, it should be clearly understood – more
clearly than it evidently is – that Ethics is a field of scholarly enquiry in
its own right, one that requires concentrated and lengthy study if it is to be
understood in any depth and applied to any real purpose or value. The application of moral reasoning to another
context of scholarly research takes considerably more than the homespun common
sense of even the most down to earth neuroscientist, if, that is,
neuroethicists are to avoid talking a load of old toot.
No comments:
Post a Comment