Monday, 7 August 2017

My Emerging Interest in Emergence

by Jon Fennell

Like much of my thinking and nearly all of my writing in recent years, my ruminations on emergence grow out of repeated encounters with Personal Knowledge by Michael Polanyi. For readers of a certain sort, the final chapter and closing sections of this book, which offer a dramatic chronicle of emergence (of life as well as of the universe generally), are extremely moving. For those who have been repeatedly disappointed by various reputed sources of meaning, Polanyi’s emergent account, founded on his unique epistemology and supported by his confessedly circular account of justification, is a much appreciated oasis in a vast and often baneful wasteland.
In 2012 I wrote a Polanyi-informed review (published in 2013) of Thomas Nagel’s strikingly honest Mind and Cosmos. During this enterprise it became clear that emergence was at the heart of Nagel’s atheistic account of a meaningful universe. But, while emergence is centrally important to both Polanyi and Nagel, Polanyi’s account is richer and more complex (though not for that reason necessarily more accurate). A comparative analysis of their underlying conceptions of emergence would have been quite fruitful in identifying their differing presuppositions. Alas, the review was already substantially beyond the allowable length for the journal in which I aimed for it to appear. So, rather than pursue the discussion, I simply noted its importance and implied that I might return to it at a later time.
As Polanyi and kindred authorities invite us to do, in the months that followed I remained open to new ideas and possibilities, allowing them freely to incubate when they arose. One such episode began when in late 2013 I read an essay by David Bentley Hart in First Things, titled ‘Emergence and Formation’. What most struck me in Hart’s article was his forthright rejection of the logic of emergence. Persistently piqued by Hart’s position, a new inquiry began to take shape. In the disarray that typically accompanies such preliminary reflection, one thing was beyond question: Polanyi was to be the vehicle by which I would move ahead.
For Hart, emergence is the ‘idea that in nature there are composite realities whose peculiar properties and capacities emerge from the interaction of their elements, even though those properties and capacities do not reside as such in those elements themselves’. He states that one such instance of (alleged) emergence is water: both hydrogen and oxygen are combustible, but water, formed by the conjunction of the two elements, is well known for its use in extinguishing fire. Hart argues that it is manifestly false to say that water is not reducible to its constituent elements. To say so is to ‘confus[e] irreducibility with identity…water’s resistance to combustion is not identical with any property resident in either hydrogen or oxygen molecules, but it is most definitely reducible to those special molecular properties that, in a particular combination, cause hydrogen and oxygen to negate one another’s combustible propensities’. He concludes, ‘At the purely material level, whatever is emergent is also reducible to that from which it emerges; otherwise, “emergence” is merely the name of some kind of magical transition between intrinsic disparate realities’.
I should quickly add that Hart is by no means a materialist, and his full position includes a critical role, as a formal cause, for the soul. Equally interesting is that Polanyi was a world-class chemist. But he is a chemist who enthusiastically embraces emergence, even, in the non-sentient domain. Take, for example, a clock. Insofar as it keeps time, the clock (which manifestly is composed of atoms, molecules, minerals, etc.) is, in light of what it does, fundamentally and ontologically different from the elements of which it is constructed. The clock, says Polanyi, is an instance of a lower level (here, a level well described by physics and chemistry) being seized by a higher level (the ‘operational principle’ measuring and telling time) and turned to its purpose. Polanyi invites us to recognize similar relations, in a hierarchical scale, between chemistry and biology, biology and physiology, physiology and (a healthy) body, the body and the intellect, and the intellect and moral and spiritual excellence. Polanyi’s emergentist account may be a corrective to the accounts offered by Nagel and Hart. It is, in any event, a comprehensive picture, given that Polanyi, consistent with evolutionary theory, but in vehement opposition to the claims of natural selection, explains in terms of emergence not only the appearance of life but also the wholly implausible but altogether remarkable existence of truth, beauty, and the good. In Polanyi’s grand drama, we find ourselves in a universe that is unfolding according to intrinsic ordering principles that, under suitable circumstances, are capable of actualizing a potential that was there from the beginning.
In coming to terms with and then writing on Polanyi’s emergentist philosophy, I soon realized that there already exists a literature on this subject. There is, moreover, a vast literature on emergence that preceded and extends beyond Polanyi. There is a reason for this. The human mind, in pursuit of the truth, is rationally led to consider emergentism. One suspects there is no other way to explain the world in which we live.


Jon M. Fennell is professor emeritus and formerly Dean of Social Sciences at Hillsdale College. Author of numerous studies on Michael Polanyi, he has also published widely on the philosophical dimensions of politics and education through essays on figures ranging from Rousseau, Dewey, and Rorty to Leo Strauss, Harry Jaffa, and C. S. Lewis.

No comments:

Post a Comment