by Simon Smith
Well, it's not easy thinking up silly titles for these things, you know; but I've committed myself now, so we're all going to have to put up with it.
This really going on a lot longer than I had
anticipated. I’ve been banging on for ages. Well, let’s see if we can’t make
this the last stop on this long and rambling trail.
Last time I
ended by suggesting that, while they may supply some interesting and often
useful context to our moral thinking, the various subdivisions of ethics don’t
really add anything to the formulation of moral principles or to the
determination of criteria for applying them. This is because the kind of
activity we’re engaged in doesn’t alter the basic moral requirements; neither
does it present us with any new moral problems. Advances in technology, to take
one example, have not created moral
problems; they’ve just re-worked the old ones.
Except that
may not be entirely true. A new moral quandary appears to have raised its
frankly disturbing head. Thanks to the wonders of modern technology, it is now
possible to make a sex doll in the form of a child. No, you didn’t misread
that. Child sex dolls are now a thing. Several months ago (July 2017) a British
man was sentenced to prison for importing and possessing a child sex doll.
There was, perhaps inevitably, more to the case than that: images of sexual
abuse, I think; but it’s the conviction for possessing the doll that caught my
attention. Though I may be wrong, this doesn’t seem like the kind of thing that
could be morally problematic without the technology to produce the doll. The
technology probably doesn’t have to be modern; I doubt whether the precise
manufacturing process and the materials involved are very important. The issue
is whether the technology and the process have produced something that invokes
moral judgement in a new way.
Let’s have
some caveats before we go any further. We are not here concerned with the
legality of the situation. The UK’s judicial processes have done what they
needed to do in that respect. We do not here presume to judge their
conclusions. No more are we concerned with the wider context of this judgement.
That this individual was very likely a significant danger to children and had,
given the possession of images, apparently exercised this capacity is, to some
degree, beside the present point. This is because moral judgement has already
been passed here: by and large, I think we might all agree that this aspect of
the situation is morally repugnant.
But let’s
leave all that aside for the moment and consider on the doll and its
possession. Intuitively, one suspects that there is something deeply disturbing
going on. The question is, what? What new kind of immorality has technology
introduced into the portfolio of human corruption and viciousness? Another,
worrying question: if this is a genuinely new moral phenomenon, is our ethical
philosophy capable of accommodating it? Will our, more or less traditional,
principles of judgement be up to the job?
For a start, I
think we can be sure that both Kantian and utilitarian philosophies are going
to struggle. On the one hand, and sticking to the issue of possession, the
categorical imperative hasn’t obviously been breached, either in terms of
universalizability of a maxim or simply by treating anyone as a means rather
than an end. It’s not even all that obvious that this individual is behaving
irrationally, assuming we regard that as relevant to moral judgement. On the
other hand, neither is it clear that possession of child sex doll, in and of
itself, causes harm to others; in principle, it might have no effect at all on
anyone else. In fact, no form of libertarianism which asserts the individual’s
freedom to do as they please in the absence of harm to others is unlikely to be
of use.
There is, of
course, a social dimension to all this, as Dr. Beauregard reminded me a few
weeks ago. The doll had to be manufactured, marketed, sold, delivered, etc.,
hardly what Mill would think of as an utterly self-regarding action. Accepting
this, however, just how it helps us clarify exactly what is morally wrong with all this remains unclear. Knowing that
other people might be affected doesn’t really add anything to the attempt to
understand how and why the effect is morally problematic.
It seems
unlikely that any kind of consequentialist ethics is going to be much good
until we have some consequences to judge. Unfortunately, it’s not at all clear
that intentionalist theories will be much better. We can’t, after all, say for
sure – purely given the possession of the doll – that this appalling douchebag
(if you’ll forgive the slip of supposed impartiality) had the intention of
harming any actual child. Even if he did – and it does seem quite likely that,
somewhere along the line he may well have – we can’t be sure that the intention
was connected to the doll, or if it was, what sort of connection it may have
been.
Given that
likelihood and high risks involved, we may be perfectly happy to accept the
judgement of the law, which we can only hope has prevented something terrible
happening. Philosophical speaking, however, this does raise questions about how
we calculate risk and likelihood in situations like this. I’m not aware of any
similar events – which doesn’t mean there aren’t any, of course – but it does
make me wonder how we come to a judgement of risk and likelihood.
That aside,
it’s still not clear how we ground ethical judgements in intentions when no intentions
have manifest themselves; or rather, the intentions which have been enacted
don’t obviously point to the harm of another person as such.
One
suggestion, again from Dr. B, is that there might be an issue of self-harm
here, though I’m not entirely convinced by that. It isn’t clear that someone
who harms him or herself really is behaving in a morally problematic way. We
may not like it; we may wish to prevent it; but can we really judge it as
immoral? It seems more likely that self-harm, however it manifests itself,
would be judged to be a symptom of something else, a matter of emotional or
psychological health rather than of moral rectitude. To make a moral case might
require further theological justification; I’m not convinced that philosophical
justification will do the job.
Besides which,
I do not take the view that self-harm is always and inevitably wrong. Just
recently, while listening to back-issues of The Bugle podcast, I was reminded of
Abdullah al-Asiri, a would-be terrorist who, in an effort to blow up a member
of the Saudi royal family, packed his bowels with high explosive and a
detonator. At least, somebody did. That’s right, he shoved a bomb up his
bumhole and tried to blow someone up. As it happens, the attempt failed; Mr. al-Asiri
succeeded only in blowing his own arse off. He did not, I believe, long survive
the attempt. In this case, not only do I not consider what Mr. al-Asiri did to
be morally wrong; I would, most assuredly concur with Messrs. Zaltzman and
Oliver in suggesting that this individual be held up as a shining example to
all terrorists. Indeed, anyone who thinks that killing other people has either
been decreed by their faith or is just a good idea should seek to model
themselves on this brave and bizarre fellow. His is the path to follow: those
bent on causing murder and mayhem must first bend over and brace themselves for
impact, as it were.
Our problem –
as opposed to Mr. al-Asiri’s many, many problems – may be that we appear to
have adopted, perhaps unwarrantably, certainly without explanation, Mill’s
basic moral criterion: viz. harm. But are we sure that harm to someone is the
only point at which moral judgement comes into play? Of course, the difficulty
there, as everyone knows, comes in trying to determine what constitutes ‘harm’.
For example, the destruction of ancient sites of great historical importance in
the Middle East by those – let’s be honest – tremendous arseholes in ISIS was a
tragedy. Was anyone actually harmed by the destruction – beyond those people
actually murdered in the process, I mean – did the act of destroying these
markers of human history, in and of itself, did it actually harm anyone? We
might say it harmed our civilisation or our humanity; it certainly made the
world a worse place. But that doesn’t seem to quite capture what we ordinarily
mean by ‘harm’. The very concept of ‘harm’ is being stretched and not obviously
in a useful way. Surely we would want to say that something very wrong, morally
wrong, was done, irrespective of whether or not anyone was actually harmed.
It seems clear
from this that neither traditional Kantian nor any kind of Utilitarian ethics
are going to be of use here. Focusing our moral thinking on how we treat
people, what we intend, and what the consequences are or may be just leads us
away from the point at issue. The question is, was there something morally
wrong with the possession of a child sex doll. Those other moral theories have
to look beyond this for harm or potential harm. It seems as though their
proponents might actually have to say, ‘no, there is nothing actually wrong
with owning a child sex doll.’ In that, I think they are mistaken. There is something very morally wrong with
possessing a child sex doll.
The question
is, what?
No comments:
Post a Comment