Sunday 11 August 2019

Endless Conversations: Meanderings on Myth and the Meaning of 'Personhood'

by Simon Smith

Einstein supposedly defined insanity as ‘doing the same thing over and over again, while expecting different results.’ I’m not sure. I’ve made pizza dough many, many times and have no intention of stopping, even if everyone begs me, for the love of God, to stop. One could call that ‘insanity’. Or ‘malice’. I prefer to think of it as ‘practising’. And yes, I do hope that one day will see a different result: viz. an edible pizza crust.
I’m exaggerating; technically, it’s always edible.
Another name for lunatic repetition might be ‘philosophy’. Not the sort wherein one reflects upon one’s values and the goals at which one aims. By ‘philosophy’, I mean the sort in which people, in full retreat from real life, abstract and conceptualise concrete relations utterly, while simultaneously over-simplifying and over-complicating everything: i.e. academic philosophy.
Philosophy often seems to be an endless reiteration of the same debates without the least hope of anyone changing their mind. Hence one reviewer’s comment on my book (still available from evil empires and not-so-evil-empires ): the arguments are perfectly sound, but it’s unlikely to convince anybody. Well, of course not. What kind of idiot would be convinced by sound logical argument?
(My favourite response was from the commentator who observed that, ‘nothing could improve this book’. Is that a complement or not?)
Or take the ever-lasting, fart-flavoured gobstopper that is philosophical realism. That realism is logically incoherent and empirically false[1] means nothing; realist philosophers remain committed to this rubbish, not for philosophical reasons, but for theological ones; and a bad theology at that.
Sadly, personalist philosophers don’t buck this trend very hard. This is frustrating because those within the tradition often regard personalism as radical, even revolutionary. When personalists foregather, however, we discuss – endlessly – the nature of ‘personhood’: what persons are or what it means to be a person. Consequently, personalism rarely gets very far or does anything very useful. And when someone does put personalist ideas to work in some concrete way, their efforts fall flat because they’re predicated on a concept of persons that hasn’t been thought through. It’s catch-22 without the funny bits.
That’s the trouble with grounding your philosophy in a single idea: if you can’t agree what the idea means, you’re stuffed.
Not all personalists don’t disagree about everything, of course. Many, for example, resist definition of the term ‘person’ because definitions risk foreclosing on meanings. Instead, they aver, there is a dynamism to ‘personhood’ which definition can’t capture. And they aver this, spite of their hidebound attachment to an antediluvian and unworkably inert metaphysics of substance.
There’s also the idea, borrowed from the late Robert Spaemann, that a person is not something but someone. This does not, I think, help us very much. Very well, we agree what persons are not; the question is, what are they? Moreover, unless we can explain what we mean by ‘thing’ without relying on the as-yet-unexplained notion ‘person’, what have we done but beg the question?
Just here, someone will almost certainly start thumping on about God. We are persons because God made us so. Quite possibly, but what have we actually explained by saying so? Sweet Jemima Crankshaft, that’s what.
And then there’s the tendency to regard ‘person’ as a moral term; that’s my particular error. Simply put, it means, to be a person, one must behave personally, i.e. treat others as persons: participate constructively in their development.[2]
Whether an essentially moral conception of ‘personhood’ explains anything is debatable. What it most assuredly doesn’t do is explain everything we might mean when talking about persons. It does not, for example, explain bad people. It just writes them out of our philosophy. But do we really want to deny that bad people are persons? Possibly, but it’s not a good idea. We don’t really want to say it’s acceptable to treat someone as an object as long as they’ve acted like an arsehole. For one thing, denying others their personhood isn’t a very personal way to behave. For another, give us each our deserts and which of us should ‘scape whipping?
Everyone is selfish or thoughtless sometimes. Who hasn’t ever pushed an old lady in front of a bus, or stolen from a homeless person, or sold drugs to children, or pandered to the fear and ignorance of a privileged majority in the name of political and economic short-termism, or contributed to the slow death of the planet, or ignored the fundamental exploitation at the heart of the global economy, or wished failure on their friends, or thrown away food despite poverty and starvation, or sacrificed a virgin to the old gods by cutting out and eating his or her heart, or deliberately hurt someone’s feelings, or deliberately hurt someone’s body, or systematically undermined the basic human rights of minority populations, or been a bit racist,[3] or punched a guinea pig in the face, or laughed when their mother fell down the stairs, or…?
What were we talking about? Oh right, persons. Again.
Conceive ‘personhood’ as a moral category, as I was wont to do, and there are some serious consequences. For a start, not everyone is a person and none of us are persons all the time. Even if we’re philosophically tough enough to take that on the chin, it still leaves the fundamental question, ‘what are we when we’re not persons?’
While I still believe that ‘personhood’ is actualised in constructive participation – for good philosophical reasons – I no longer do so as insistently as I once did. Clearly, to account for the complexity of real life, we must accept that constructive participation is only one form of ‘personhood’. There are others and they won’t all be nice. 
The trouble with all this talk about persons is that, even if we agree that persons aren’t something, we still seem to be thinking about persons as some ‘thing’. We’re trying to find a way of talking about this – what? Entity? Being? Substance? But aren’t they just different ways of trying not to say thing or ‘thing’ while still very definitely thinking it? They are.
Taking a leaf out of Farrer’s book,[4] the solution to this, and to the broader question of what ‘personhood’ means, is not to solidify the self but to liquidate it. Accept it: there’s no such thing as a person. Not because persons aren’t objects (or ‘objects’) but because, in one philosophically crucial sense, they don’t exist at all. ‘Person’ is a myth; that is, a story that becomes true in the telling and, more importantly, the living of it. You are, in short, the story of your life. No more no less.
Naturally, some stories are better, i.e. healthier, than others. They contribute to our development, our ability to fulfil our potential and become what we may. Such stories will be constructive, participative: they put us in harmony with others and the world, not just interactively but interconstitutively.  Other stories, I’m sure, aren’t constructive or healthy at all. They may be stories of separation and difference, of the other as a threat, something to be feared and hated. Some are about the ossification and isolation of the self. And we don’t always choose what kind of stories we live. We may choose some, but we’re also born into stories, many of which we simply accept as being true. Who we are and who we become depends on the interplay between these two kinds of story: the one’s we create and the ones we accept, often without realising.
But surely that’s another oversimplification. Are there really only two kinds of story at work in any life? Clearly not. The interlacing web of narratives within which we structure our lives is far more complicated. It will, most likely, comprise of healthy bits and unhealthy bits: i.e. bits wherein we strive to fulfil ourselves and support others in doing likewise and bits where we seek to defeat ourselves and others with selfishness and rodent punching. Quite likely there are also long periods where we stand around scratching our arses and picking our noses because we can’t think of anything good to do.
Before anyone starts muttering about how stories need or better still, entail, storytellers, we’ve already been through that back in April, while thumping on about Derrida.
Of this I am certain: there are no storytellers outside of the stories we tell; we are made of myths. The person I am began life as a character in the story of others: viz., my family. The story they told about me was a story about someone who would make up his own story. This, I have attempted to do. Not with any marked success, mind.
We’re made of myths. That’s probably why evidence and reasoned argument don’t change people’s minds, whereas a good, or at least oft repeated, story will.
Is that the end of the conversation? Unlikely, I’m afraid.
One last thought. There’s a theological problem that’s been bugging me for years, almost since I began my studies. It’s this: once we realise that God-talk is, as it absolutely must be, analogical, metaphorical, mythical, is a life of faith still possible? Otherwise put, can one live a life in real, personal relation to metaphors and myths as religious praxis demands? The answer, evidently, is ‘yes, we do it all the time’. Money, power, economics, politics, technology: all these are myths, stories we tell. Gender is a myth; even individuality is a myth: disconnect the individual from the network of physical and social connections which constitutes her environment and what’s left? Nothing at all.
Given that our entire lives are constituted by a matrix of interconnecting myths, conceptual maps wherein we plot the course of our existence, the idea of living one’s life in relation to the myths that we call ‘religion’ poses no difficulty at all.
 In fact, the real question isn’t, ‘can we live our lives in relation to myths and metaphors?’ It’s ‘can we live without them?’



[1] And yes, before anyone points it out, I know perfectly well that this is an oxymoron: a logically incoherent proposition – such as any claim to know mind-independent reals – can’t very well be empirically anything, let alone false. Except, of course, in real life which is frequently much more complicated and more interesting than logic. On the other hand, this is one of the reasons I find expressions like ‘anti-realist’ so irritating. The idea, propagated by philosophers, that any rejection of realism must constitute ‘anti-realism’ is nonsense and very bad philosophy. You, or more precisely, I can’t be against something which doesn’t make any sense. It would be like coming out against square circles!
[2] Yes, that does mean that persons are actualised in action: we are what we do and if you don’t like it, feel free to do one yourself. (It’s a Northern English vernacular expression; Google it).
[3] Being racist about the French is still racist, I’m afraid.
[4] That book being Faith and Speculation (London: Adam & Charles Black, 1967), 167.

No comments:

Post a Comment