by Simon Smith
I’ve been turning something a bit
Derridean over in my mind recently. It was, in part, sparked by someone (can’t
remember who) mentioning Jacques Derrida’s visit to the University of Sussex in
1997 (I think). I was a mere stripling at the time, about to finish my
undergraduate degree in philosophy and go out into the big wide world. Well,
Brighton. The man himself was everything any of us could have hoped for:
brilliant, enigmatic, French. He wore a broad-brimmed black hat and a black
cape; I remember him as carrying a stick, but that might not be true since
memory paints it as a silver top cane, which at the time I hoped was a
sword-stick. I still do. Derrida looked every inch the Continental Philosopher,
an intellectual hero in the oh-so Romantic tradition. Next to the shabby fuc–
individuals who populated the philosophy department at Sussex, he was very,
very cool.
He was also
quite incomprehensible, at least as far as this particular shabby individual
was concerned. Understood nary a word of it. Impressed, I most assuredly was,
but.
Since then,
things have changed little. True, I’m no longer an undergraduate, shabby or
otherwise. I even tuck my shirt in all the way round sometimes. I still
wouldn’t claim to have a fulsome or especially clear grasp of Derrida’s
philosophy, but I believe I have some idea as to what’s occurring and I’m
working on it, insofar as it might turn out to be useful.
My rather
loose noodling around with the Man in the Black Hat, came a bit more into focus
recently when talking at a friend: viz. Dr James Beauregard also of this
digital parish. I say, ‘talking at;’ it began as conversation, but I had, in Jamesian
fashion (M.R., not Old Bill), ‘fallen somewhat into the tone of a lecturer.’ I
suspect that, on the other end of the email, Jim ‘was feeling a little restive
under… [my] harangue.’ And I dahn’t blame ‘im niyver.
In an effort
to give that harangue still more focus, perhaps to the stage where it might, to
slight some degree, begin to make sense, I decided to set it down here for the
delectation and edification of any who might happen this way.
The discussion was, as is so
often the case with Jim and I, about the nature of persons. I was maintaining a
dynamic view: persons as persons-in-action, persons-in-relation (hooray!). Jim
holds out for the ontological priority (whatever that means) of persons apart
from action and relation in line with an older, metaphysic of the inert and the
static (boo!). What set me off about Derrida was a comment to the effect that,
in order to have relations or actions or anything of the sort, we need at least
two somethings to do the relating or acting.
As it happens, I wouldn’t automatically disagree with this claim, except when being deliberately difficult or obtuse. In a purely philosophical mood, however, it all depends on the logical status of the word ‘need’. Where ‘need’ signifies necessity or entailment relations – which it doesn’t actually need to do, as it were – the claim is certainly false. When we look at the fundamental constituents of the universe, we find that there are no actual things at all, only (but not just, no never just) the constant interplay of process: rhythmic patterns of energy or activity interconnecting like the bejaysus. There are no things to relate.
On the other hand, if ‘need’ means ‘presupposes,’
then Jim is basically correct, especially at the higher level of personal
action: relations do presuppose relata
just as actions presuppose agents. But that just means, in order to talk about
or make sense of ideas like ‘relation’ and ‘action,’ we need the idea of agents
to do the relating or acting. Logically speaking, it’s a requirement not a condition. This gives us something
a little looser and more flexible to replace rigid and supposedly watertight
entailment relations. Presuppositional logic is, incidentally, how
intentionality works: the intended, as Austin Farrer very nearly said but didn’t,
presupposes the intending, the act presupposes the agent.
As an existence claim, this allows plenty of
room for being wrong. I could, after all, be wrong about the circumstances I
interpret as personal action. It might be a natural event, like the wind or the
tides. Isn’t that the real meaning of magic and superstition, ghosties and
ghoulies and the like? So we’re told. When I look at the stars, I might imagine
that I see figures or symbols, figures and symbols presumably put there by
somebody. But maybe I’m wrong. Maybe it’s just a lot of flaming gas balls
scattered across the night sky and I’m projecting the symbols and figures onto
them.
Mind.
Blown.
Blown.
The
point is, presuppositional logic allows for mistakes: what looks like personal
activity (the placing of astral bodies in particular patterns) is actually
nothing of the sort; it looks that
way but isn’t really.
To put it
another way, we can’t draw the inference any tighter because what counts as an
intentional action is always going to be a matter of interpretation. And this
is true, even when it’s something someone does; even, for that matter, when
it’s something you or I do. We set out to do something
deliberately, intentionally, and we do something else by accident or mistake.
You pick up a glass of what looks like beer, but it turns out to be another
kind of yellow fizzing liquid (though why someone put that in a beer glass is a mystery). This very evening, I set out to
make a very nice curry. In so doing, I singularly failed. My intentional action
went badly awry and what I actually made was a bit of a weird mess with too
much vinegar and way too much tamarind. I did not deliberately or intentionally
create a weird mess; that was an accident. Honest.
I’m actually a
pretty good cook, if you want to know. Ask anybody. The only person I’ve even
remotely poisoned is my father; and that, only a couple of times thus far.
In any case,
the point is—
Wait, what’s that strange burning
sensation in my thro….ack ack aaarrrgh?!
Thud!
No comments:
Post a Comment