Thursday, 21 December 2017

Looking at the Sun: Chapter Summary

Technology: A View from Personalism
Part 2


by James Beauregard

In the previous blog I brought up the issue of the philosophy of technology, something to which personal lists have not dedicated as much attention as they have to other topics. Philosophy of technology, though, has continued to develop and today there are numerous views of how technology should be conceived approached, developed etc. I mentioned the personalist philosopher Romano Guardini, whose Letters from Lake Como is one of the few sustained reflections on technology from the perspective of personalism. He follows that work in the 1920s, and from the mid to late 20th century, and now into the 21st, reflections on philosophy of technology have continued to develop.
Contemporary writing on technology has continued this discussion, and added to it a focus on technological artifacts in and of themselves, and their impact on us. In reviewing contemporary philosophies of technology, Thomas A. C. Reydon characterised such philosophies as containing three components:

(1) the systematic clarification of the nature of technology as an element and product of human culture;
(2) the systematic reflection on the consequences of technology for human life;
(3) the systematic investigation of the practices of engineering, invention, designing and making of things.[1]

Recently, a philosopher Mark S. Latkovic wrote an article called "Thinking about Technology from a Catholic Moral Perspective."[2] In this article, he delineates 10 distinct ways that philosophers and theologians have considered technology, several of which are, I think, useful to personalist thought, whether moving from philosophical or theological personalism:
Technology as Ambiguous Instrument. Referencing Pope Emeritus Benedict XVI, this model sees technology as having both positive and negative aspects linked to our freedom and autonomy. Technology embodies and ever-present risk of encouraging in its users an arrogant, Promethean attitude. In Benedict’s words, “Technology is never merely technology. It reveals man and his aspirations toward development, it expresses the inner tension that impels him gradually to overcome material limitations,”[3] and of equal importance, “human freedom is authentic only when it responds to the fascination of technology with decisions that are the fruit of moral responsibility.”[4]
Technology as Subordinated to Ethics. Drawing on the work of Karol Wojtyla, both as philosopher and in his writings as Pope John Paul II, this model looks to the way we think about technology, its artefacts and its consequences, in the interests of respecting human dignity, maintaining throughout “the priority of ethics over technology,” and “the primacy of person over things.”[5] Latkovic captures the position in this statement: “We should always treat persons as ends and treat technology as means.”[6]
Technology as Liberating Force. This model takes a generally positive view of technology, with the economist George Gilder as one of its proponents. Drawing on information theory, Gilder views technology as liberating us from many of the drudgeries of daily living. He emphasises the role of human creativity vis à vis technology as liberating force.
Technology as Gift of the Holy Spirit. Drawing on Dominican theologian Benedict Ashley, this model is grounded in an explicitly Christian vision in which science and technology are viewed as “God’s gift to humanity as well as products of human creativity.”[7] A key notion in Ashely’s position is that of stewardship, seeing technological development and use as sources of service to God and the human community.[8]
There is substantial content here for looking at technology from a personalist perspective. Such reflection might begin with asking what distinct or original contribution personalist philosophy might make to the philosophy of technology. In reflecting on the literature of technology and of personalism, I want to suggest that I think that, in order to develop a philosophy of technology from a personalist point of view, it is necessary to consider three interrelated aspects:

(1) A robust understanding of persons;
(2) A nuanced understanding of technology as relational, as artefacts created by, influenced by, and influencing persons;
(3) A balanced understanding of individual good and common good as they impact on persons and technology.

With these components in mind I would like to present an initial attempt at considering philosophy of technology from a distinctly personalist perspective:
A Personalist Philosophy of Technology is a manner of considering technology that is grounded in and flows from an anthropology of acting persons adequately understood, which examines the artefacts/instruments created and used by persons in relation, and the bi-directional influence between persons and technology in multiple domains, from the individual to the social, and in a manner that is ordered to the individual good and the common good. Given that the use of technology is a human/personal activity, and as such can be good or evil in its inception, creation, intentions, actions, ends and consequences (both foreseen and unforeseen), ethics ought to have primacy over technology in each of these aspects.
Consider that a first attempt at thinking through the issue of technology from a personalist perspective that is simultaneously a call to personalist philosophers to bring their own philosophical knowledge to bear on an increasingly important issue facing the human race.




[1] T.A.C. Reydon, “Philosophy of Technology,” in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. I have explored some of these ideas though with an explicit focus on the field of neuroethics in the public square, in “Personalismo Ontológico Moderno en la Plaza Pública: Hacia una personalista neuroética”, paper presented at the Asociación Española de Personalismo conference, X Jornadas de la AEP Spanish Personalist Association conference, May 5, 2016 “¿Qué es filosofía? ¿Y para qué sirve?”, Universidad Francisco de Vitoria, Madrid, Spain
[2] M. S. Latkovic, “Thinking about Technology from a Catholic Moral Perspective” National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 15:4 (Winter) 2015: 687-699.
[3] Benedict XVI, Encyclical Caritasin veritate, n. 69. 
[4] Benedict XVI, Encyclical Caritas in veritate, nn. 74-75.
[5] John Paul II, Redemptor Hominis, no 16.
[6] Latkovic, 697. Wojtyla formulated his personalistic norm in 1960, stating “This norm, in its negative aspect, states that the person is the kind of good which does not admit of use and cannot be treated as an object of use and as such the means to an end. In its positive form the Personalistic norm confirms this: the person is a good towards which the only proper and adequate attitude is love.” Karol Wojtyla, Love and Responsibility, Trans. H.T. Willets. San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1993.
[7] Latkovic, 694.
[8] Latkovic, 694.

No comments:

Post a Comment