Sunday 12 January 2020

Mirror of the Cosmos: Farrerian Reflections on Mind and Nature, Again!

by Simon Smith

Apologies once again for the extended interruption to our usual service. This time it was cause by a) Christmas and all its associated indulgences (yes, I had a slight hangover); and b) the contraction of foul and hideous diseases (I had a cold). Having now fully recovered from both a) and b) we may now proceed with our sexy adventures in cosmological consciousness. Oh yeah!

Oh wait, it looks as though there may actually be some consequences to all this hot and dirty philosophical business. Uh oh.

Part 4: Where Do Babies Come From? 
Analogical thinking rests on our ability to recognise other modes of reality as being active agencies. But how do I know what active agency looks like? From my own case, rebounds the echo of ego-certainty. Perhaps; but in such truisms, lurks pernicious circularity. How did I come to be an agency capable of recognising its reflection in others? Where did “my own case” come from? Where else, P. F. Strawson observed, if not those others? A “case” is not a single integer. Arguments “from” are really arguments “back to”; they return us to the simple ontological facts of human existence.
   Logical philosophers will doubtless remind us that we have known as much since Strawson and Wittgenstein located the primary conditions for any thought at all in those who taught us how to think. Unearthing the roots of thought and action, however, it becomes clear that, as vital as their corrective was, those logical philosophers still somehow missed the point. After all, Farrer observed, ‘[i]t is not as though we believed in our neighbour’s personality because logical philosophers are able to exhibit the self-contradiction involved in denying it’.[1] Such intellectual conceit surely adds the insult of unnecessary demonstration to the injury of inexcusable doubt: bad faith atop faulty inference. “The other” is no philosophical puzzle for rational minds to solve but a matter of real practical urgency.
This is because our first encounter with others finds us supremely helpless. John Macmurray (Farrer’s tutor at Balliol) put the point with paradoxical perspicuity. We are, he said, ‘“adapted”…to being unadapted,’ that is, ‘“adapted” to a complete dependence’ on others.[2] The nursling has no control over her bodily movements, no capacity to initiate action or deliberately do anything. Her basic experience, therefore, cannot be the exercise of her own agency; for she is not an agent. Rather, that experience can only be of the agency first exercised on her by others. Therein lie the analogical foundations upon which our understanding of other agencies must rest.
Indeed, our primitive experience of another’s ‘disturbance-effect’ is likely why psychological development begins with the objectified ‘I’. The child conceives herself first as an object, innocent as the philosophical realist and as devoid of any other possible perspective. She is a thing in a world where all perspectives are one perspective; that is, her own; though, again like the realist, she does not know this. Her subjectivity, she later acquires as part of the process of learning that neither she nor her world are so ontologically or psychologically transparent.
This marks a subtle but important shift in personalist schematics. Traditionally, we are told that persons arise only in dialogue, between I and Thou. In a sense, however, studies in developmental psychology suggest otherwise. It seems that an I only develops when a Thou encounters an It and transforms it into and I.
To such subjectifying transformations we are well “adapted”; indeed, perfectly so. In Macmurray’s words, we are ‘made to be cared for’; and cared for we must be if we are to survive long. Being so “adapted”, how fortuitous then that we are born into a manifold of personal agencies or, to warm the face of such schematics, a world of families and friends, of inherently personal love-relationships. Farrer concurred with his former teacher: ‘[f]rom first infancy,’ he said, ‘our elders loved us, played us, served us and talked us into knowing them’. Had they failed us, we would not be.
Consciousness, then, is awakened, better still invested, in us by those who supply the mental resources with which we explore our world and ourselves. By means of such investments, the enquiring mind, takes its first steps. Our parents and teachers give us the tools with which we shape our own part in transactions: physical and metaphysical, cosmological and psychological. Before that, however
We learnt to talk, because [others] talked to us; and to like, because they smiled at us. Because we could first talk, we can now think; that is, we can talk silently to the images of the absent, or… pretend to be our own twin, and talk to ourself.[3]

Others supply the conditions of our conduct, both mode and circumstance of developing personality. I can think, that is, talk to myself, because they first talked to me and taught me to reply. I can even think “objectively”, that is, abstract from the immediacy of my experience, because they taught me rules for consistently organising and interpreting it. These rules, they called theories: scientific, philosophical, psychological, etc.; they mitigate the particularity of my perspective by co-opting me into a community of explorers, so make me one of them. In Farrer’s words, ‘[t]hought is the interiorisation of dialogue’.[4] Staking its claim to the terms and the structure of those transactions, the image of the other is thereby internalised, instilling the “self” with what Feuerbach called ‘the inner life of man’, our social self, our ‘species being’.[5]
The seemingly “objective” self of our psychological infancy is thereby displaced. Internalised otherness contrasts itself with that “externalised” or “objective” self. The nascent “self”, its needs, activities, and perspective, are passed through the image of the other. Being “filtered” in this way, the “self” is (re)evaluated and (re)constructed in relation to the other. In short, I learn to double myself so as to play the part of another within myself.[6] Colloquially, one might say I become a “self” by learning to put myself in the place of the other. The I is formed by re-enacting that place, that primary otherness. Being Thou unto others, the “self” is, to reiterate a favourite Feuerbachian phrase, essentially ‘species being’. Thus, the transactional structure of social conscience and conscious action are built-into the mode and act of self-construction by the other.
This overrules any ontological privilege or priority the ‘I’ might claim over interpersonal connections. Prior actuality, as Farrer dubbed it, cannot belong to the “self” for ‘mentality always was a social, not a solitary, thing.’[7] Metaphysically and psychologically, priority resides in the other for that is where my “self” is born. The “self” becomes a “self” only by being appropriated by others and learning to appropriate them in turn.

Oh yeah! That’s what I’m talking about! And I’ve been talking about it for ages! Now I’m trying to make it sound sexy by talking in this exaggerated way with lots of exclamation marks and playing 70s guitar wah-wah music in the background! Mmm, sexy metaphysics!
So come back next week – almost definitely next week, or the week after at the latest – for another instalment in Metaphysics: Down and Dirty Business! 



[1] Farrer, Faith and Speculation, 129, my emphasis.
[2] Macmurray, J. Persons in Relation, (New Jersey/London: Humanities Press International Inc., 1991), 48.
[3] Farrer, ‘Thinking the Trinity’ in A Celebration of Faith, ed. Leslie Houlden (London: Hodder & Stoughton, 1970), 74.
[4] Farrer, Faith and Speculation, 126.
[5] Feuerbach, L. The Essence of Christianity, trans. George Eliot, (New York: Harper & Row, 1957), 2.
[6] Feuerbach, 83.
[7] Farrer, ‘Thinking the Trinity’ in A Celebration of Faith, 74.


No comments:

Post a Comment